Because
juries have the right to nullify, judges have the obligation to give proper instructions "You
must be crazy," French psychiatrists told Phillipe Pinel in 1792 after Pinel
announced his intention to free the mentally ill from the shackles and bonds that kept
them tightly chained to cold and filthy institutional walls and beds. "They are
dangerous and violent and will kill us all," Pinel was repeatedly warned. Yet, his
loosening of the chains was the foremost affirmative act that encouraged a wave of humane
treatment finally leading to relief and cure.
"Don't put fluoride in the water," critics screamed in the late 1940s.
"You will destroy the health and water supply of innocent people." Once again,
however, the naysayers were proven wrong.
Today, Chicken Little's "the sky is falling" argument thunders through
American courtrooms as judges march lockstep to the tune that jury nullification will
produce "anarchy," the favorite word used by judges ostensibly as a reasoned
discourse against the nullification position. Interestingly, unlike Pinel and fluoride,
which brought something new to society, the "nullification is anarchy" refrain
sounds fervently despite the fact that nullification has been the rule of law in all but
the last century, and remains the rule of law in a few states, like Maryland and Indiana,
where, not surprisingly, anarchy has not resulted.
In general, the exercise of "jury nullification" involves the refusal of the
jury to convict a defendant if, acting as the conscience of the community under the United
States Supreme Court's formulation in Duncan v. Louisiana, the jury believes it unjust to
apply the law as written to the facts of the case. In short, the jury exercises its
discretion for mercy by saying that it would be wrong to stigmatize the defendant as a
criminal in that particular case.
Actually, everyone concedes the jury has the power to nullify, to extend mercy to some
hapless souls who get trapped in the netherworld between law and justice. Because the
founders of our republic themselves had been caught in that netherworld, they lodged
ultimate power in the people, not in the government. No person may be convicted of an
offense without the verdict of a jury of peers. John Adams, one of the more conservative
leaders of this period, expressed the prevailing sentiments in his diary in 1771:
"Now, should the melancholy case arise that the judges should give their opinions to
the jury against one of these fundamental principles, is a juror obliged to find his
verdict generally, according to this direction, or even to find the fact specially and
submit the law to the court? Every man of any feeling or conscience, will answer no. It is
not only his right, but his duty, in that case to find the verdict according to his own
best understanding, judgment, and conscience, though in direct opposition to the
directions of the court."
As I write this essay, I am mindful that it will be published in a newspaper. In
colonial America, publishing truthful statements against the government was seditious
libel carrying severe criminal penalties. It took a nullifying jury in the famous case of
John Peter Zenger to establish the freedom of the press we all enjoy today. Judges then
dutifully sent law violators to prison whose only crime was to tell a truth about the
government. A courageous jury in 1725 freed Zenger, who was technically guilty under the
law. Had they not done so, today's magazine and newspaper readers would only be seeing the
government's side of this and every other issue.
Commentators have determined that nullification was the prevalent rule since the
inception of the jury. It was only at the end of the last century that courts began to
severely restrict the authority jurors had enjoyed for centuries. The first two-thirds of
this century witnessed the near extinction of the sovereignty of the jury to acquit on the
basis of conscience. Arguments favoring jury nullification were resurrected in the late
1960s to counter the maneuvering of government prosecutors to obtain convictions of its
more vocal opponents during the Vietnam war era. Since that time, most legal commentators
who have written on this issue have favored nullification, though there remains
disagreement over what exactly it is.
Because it is clear that jurors have the power to nullify, the modern argument concerns
whether the jury has the right to be instructed of its power to nullify. The central
question is, "May the jurors be instructed as to their power, in rare cases, to
refuse to convict a defendant if, acting as the conscience of a community, the jurors
believe it would be unjust to punish the defendant?" Once this question is asked, the
right issue can be explored: Is it ever wise for a jury to exercise mercy?
Since 1972, when my first article on jury nullification was published in the Southern
California Law Review, I have argued a cautious "yes." I do not believe that
juries have the right to rewrite laws, or to disregard laws they do not like. But juries
do not do that, as the major jury studies demonstrate, and they cannot do that, for no
jury has the power to alter or repeal legislation. Jury nullification is merely a
discretionary refusal to apply the law announced by the judge to a setting it may not have
been intended to govern. General laws need particularized application if justice is to be
served. In rare cases, where laws are being used oppressively or unfairly, the jury may
say "no." Murderers, rapists, thieves and scoundrels are not likely to be freed
by big-hearted juries. These are not the cases jury nullification affects.
The term "jury nullification" appears to connote jurors violating the law and
violating their oaths. As Professor George Fletcher has noted, the term ". . . is
unfortunate and misleading, because it suggests that when the jury votes its conscience,
it is always engaged in an act of disrespect toward the law. The acquittal, supposedly,
nullifies the law. In place of the law, it is said, the jury interposes its own moral
judgment or political preferences."
Fletcher rejects the belief that jury nullification is an affront to the rule of law,
and he provides a healthier image for the practice of it:
"[T]he function of the jury as the ultimate authority on the law [is] not to
nullify' the instructions of the judge, but to complete the law, when necessary, by
recognizing principles of justification that go beyond the written law. It would be better
if we abandon the phrase jury nullification' and spoke instead of the jury's
function in these cases of completing and perfecting the positive law recognized by the
courts and the legislature."
Every once in a while, a case arises that does not fit the general mold. Such a case
was presented in a brilliant PBS television documentary on Frontline, entitled
"Inside the Jury Room," that filmed an actual jury deliberation. Leroy Reed, a
sincere but dull-witted man, was arrested by his parole officer for illegal possession of
a weapon. Reed, who enjoyed the television detective The Enforcer and fancied becoming a
private investigator himself, received a mail-order detective course that said he would
need a gun. Reed obediently bought one, not fully realizing his actions violated a
condition of his parole. No one in the courtroom doubted that Reed was only vaguely aware
of why he was on trial and what he had done wrong. He had not caused harm, was not likely
to cause harm, and certainly did not have any intent to cause harm or violate rules.
Convicting him would be like rebuking a 5-year-old for not knowing algebra. Under the
technical wording of the law, however, Reed was guilty. His defense lawyer pleaded for a
jury nullification instruction, but the trial judge called it "an invitation to
anarchy."
Once in the jury room, it was clear that the jurors were unanimous about two things:
under the law, Reed was guilty; morally, he was innocent. The just thing to do would be to
acquit him, but the jurors had been told only that they had to follow the letter of the
law. What should they do? During the spirited two-hour debate, some jurors argued that
their oath required that they convict even though it meant doing an injustice. Others
argued that they must follow what conscience told them was the right thing to do in this
case. Both sides, however, seemed upset that the law had left them in this predicament. In
the end, the conscience arguments swept over the last remaining holdout. When he
reluctantly retreated from his belief that the jury had no moral leeway, a verdict was
reached. Leroy Reed was acquitted, and several jurors went home having less respect for
the legal system than when they had first reported for jury duty.
Unless juries can exercise mercy in these cases, they can never fulfill their
constitutional function as the conscience of the community. Without "jury
nullification," properly understood, the "conscience of the community"
language in Supreme Court opinions including Duncan v. Louisiana is empty rhetoric.
My reasons for supporting jury nullification are based on historical research (which
demonstrates that juries did not abuse their power), pragmatic values (which suggest that
better jury verdicts will come from juries that are given the option to nullify in tough
cases) and democratic principles (which teach that jury nullification is directly linked
to participatory government of, by and for the people). Clay S. Conrad, in his new book
Jury Nullification: The Evolution of a Doctrine, provides ample support that jury
nullification is an essential part of our government system.
Currently, an even more pressing development encourages judicial instructions to
juries. As noted by Joan Biskupic in a February Washington Post story about juror protest,
millions of potential jurors now have some concept of jury nullification and believe it to
be their fundamental right. Judges lately have been attempting to weed jury panels of
persons familiar with the nullification concept, but such procedures are constitutionally
questionable and ultimately impractical as the numbers of knowledgeable potential jurors
grow larger. Many, and perhaps most, potential jurors have an incorrect view of what
nullification is and when it should be exercised.
Furthermore, we live in the world's largest yet most successful melting pot with
diversity of views as the norm, not the deviation. Even without judicial instruction on
nullification, jurors will vote their beliefs anyway. Judicial instructions are now
essential to explain to jurors the purposes, limitations and dangers that make
nullification an important part of our constitutional democracy.
Failure of judges properly to instruct jurors on their power to acquit could in fact
ironically bring about a judicially created anarchy. |
Jury
nullification deprives the accused and the state of knowing what is legal, violating due
process Listen to a proponent of jury nullification for more than about five
minutes, and you'll likely discover a person who is upset about something; a person who
feels put upon by society's injustices; who's mad as hell and isn't going to take it
anymore. This is not to say that all proponents of jury nullification are extremists from
the right or left or elsewhere (although it is perhaps symptomatic of jury nullification's
problems that some of its more vocal supporters include people who are very politically
active, such as members of the National Rifle Association, gun control advocates, abortion
rights supporters, pro-life groups, those who support legalizing marijuana, militia groups
and tax protesters), or that a legitimate sounding argument in favor of nullification
cannot be made (usually supported by selectively chosen historical examples from a time
when juries were virtually the only forum for resisting the king's tyranny). In fact, the
law reviews have become saturated in recent years with articles from reasonable-sounding
proponents and opponents of jury nullification, and several day-long symposiums on the
topic have been sponsored around the country. So there must be some good reasons for
supporting jury nullification, right?
I don't think so. When all of the rhetorical dust has settled, we come back to the
fundamental reality that jury nullification happens only when one or more members of a
jury is so disaffected with conditions in society and so angry about the result which the
law appears to require in a particular case, that the juror is willing to ignore the law
as given to the jury by the court and to cast his or her vote contrary to law. I am
against having jurors make decisions based on anger, fear, resentment or pique. I don't
want "12 angry men" who decide based upon their personal predilections and
prejudices. The risk of injustice and error is just too great with that mix of emotions
and subjectivity.
Arguments about jury nullification are often fought over such issues as (1) whether
jury nullification is a "power" (it is, in the sense that with a general verdict
in a criminal case, courts can only rarely see or do anything about nullification in
action) or a "right" (it is not, with two exceptions noted below, since when a
juror is identified by other jurors as unwilling to deliberate and follow the law, the
court can disqualify the juror); (2) whether the jury should be notified of its
"power" to nullify (courts have unanimously rejected instructions telling jurors
about nullification); (3) whether race-based nullification should be encouraged as an
antidote to a criminal justice system perceived as being heavily biased against
African-Americans; and (4) whether a juror's indication of his or her unwillingness to
follow the law is grounds for removal (it is, although the standard is very high since
courts are properly reluctant to involve themselves too much in the substance of jury
deliberations).
Although these are analytically distinct questions and might admit of differing
answers, proponents of nullification usually answer all of the questions one way, and
opponents usually answer all of the questions the other way (except for the question about
race-based nullification, which generates conflicting viewpoints). The debate is not over
the details; it is over the underlying wisdom and validity of nullification.
Institutionalized jury nullification, formally sanctioned by the law, is not entirely
unknown to our legal landscape. The constitutions of Maryland and Indiana expressly
provide that, in a criminal case, the jury is to decide questions of both fact and law.
The judge's instructions on the law are advisory only. This gives criminal juries in
Maryland and Indiana the power, right and constitutional duty to decide for themselves
what the law is in a particular case, and that is the essence of jury nullification - the
power to ignore the law as given to the jury by the judge. We don't hear loud cries from
Maryland and Indiana about chaos, anarchy and disrespect for the rule of law. So maybe
nullification isn't such a bad thing; maybe we can trust juries after all. Or, maybe the
cultures and citizenry in Maryland and Indiana are so homogeneous that giving the jury the
power to decide the law in criminal cases has no significant practical impact. I was born
and raised in Indianapolis, and my sense is that there is a much greater homogeneity in
that state than in, say, California or New York. I doubt that the experiences in Maryland
and Indiana would be duplicated elsewhere.
In any event, nullification should be rejected for more basic reasons. Giving the jury
the power to declare what the law is or to ignore the law entirely is inconsistent with
fundamental notions of separation of powers, equal protection, due process and respect for
the rule of law. (I hesitate to use the phrase "rule of law" in the wake of the
impeachment proceedings, but I trust readers to differentiate between the political
process of impeachment, where the phrase "rule of law" was primarily a
rhetorical device employed by political advocates, and the judicial process of a real
trial, where the "rule of law" still has meaning.)
Jury nullification frustrates the separation of powers because it arrogates to the
judicial branch, acting through the jury, the power to ignore the law as enacted by the
legislative and executive branches. The judicial branch's role is not to pass upon the
wisdom of a statute; it is only to pass upon its constitutionality. Once having determined
that a statute is constitutional, the judicial branch is obliged to apply the statute as
drafted and intended. I don't want judges or juries to pick and choose at their whim which
laws they will or will not enforce. The people elected representatives and a governor to
engage in lawmaking. Those laws should not be undermined by judges (who, although
technically elected, are not intended to be representatives of the electorate) or by
jurors (who are selected by trial counsel whose primary goal is to win, not represent the
public).
Jury nullification violates equal protection because the results in individual cases
depend not upon the fair and even-handed application of the law to like situations, but
upon the arbitrary refusal to apply the law to like situations. I use the word
"arbitrary" in a special sense here. A particular juror may have internally
consistent and even rational-sounding reasons for refusing to follow the law. For example,
a juror might decide not to convict someone of a gun possession charge because of a firmly
held belief that such laws are unconstitutional in light of the Second Amendment. However,
I would treat this as an arbitrary refusal to apply the law in light of the current state
of cases interpreting the Second Amendment. From the law's perspective, the juror who
places his or her faith in the Second Amendment is acting arbitrarily and capriciously.
The results in individual prosecutions should not depend upon such arbitrary factors as
whether a Second Amendment devotee happens to be on the jury.
Jury nullification violates principles of due process because it deprives the accused
and the state of the ability to know in advance what conduct is legal or illegal. This
basic due process protection finds expression in the ex post facto clause, in rules
against vagueness in criminal statutes, and in the constitutional doctrine forbidding
prosecution under laws where no reasonable person would expect there to be any obligation
to act in a particular way. A defendant should not be exposed to the possibility of
criminal penalties because a jury decided to ignore laws providing an affirmative defense
or creating or implementing constitutional protections. And, while jury nullification is
most often invoked to secure acquittals, once the cat is released from the cage, there is
precious little to control its appetite. Jury nullification to secure convictions is a
clear risk (although judicial review of such convictions would cure some of the damage, it
is inevitable that some of these convictions would be affirmed, resulting in unjust
confinement).
Finally, jury nullification undermines the rule of law. The remarkable resilience of
our constitutional form of government lies precisely in its rejection of law by personal
fiat. Separation of powers is grounded in the same distrust of the concentration of too
much power in too few hands. Ours is a cooperative form of governance, and our justice
system depends upon those same cooperative elements. We permit great decisions to be made
in our courts of justice only because we trust the participants, judges, jurors, counsel
and witnesses to come together with dignity and with a sense of public responsibility to
do the people's work. That trust would be sorely tested by a doctrine which celebrates the
power of a single person to impose his or her personal beliefs upon a process that is
designed and intended to reflect law and justice at its best. |